INTRODUCTION
Amy Gutmann
"SERIOUSNESS
is, for a certain kind of artist, an imperative uniting the aesthetic
and the
ethical," John Coetzee wrote in Giving
Offense: Essays on Censorship. In The
Lives of Animals, the 1997-98 Tanner Lectures at Princeton
University, John
Coetzee displays the kind of seriousness that can unite aesthetics and
ethics.
Like the typical Tanner Lectures, Coetzee's lectures focus on an
important
ethical issue-the way human beings treat animals-but the form of
Coetzee's
lectures is far from the typical Tanner Lectures, which are generally
philosophical essays. Coetzee's lectures are fictional in form: two
lectures
within two lectures, which contain a critique of a more typical
philosophical
approach to the topic of animal rights. Coetzee prompts us to imagine
an
academic occasion (disconcertingly like the Tanner Lectures) in which
the
character Elizabeth Costello, also a novelist, is invited by her hosts
at
Appleton College to deliver two honorific lectures on a topic of her
choice.
Costello surprises her hosts by not delivering lectures on literature
or
literary criticism, her most apparent areas of academic expertise.
Rather she
takes the opportunity to discuss in detail what she views as a "crime
of
stupefying proportions" that her academic colleagues and fellow human
beings routinely and complacently commit: the abuse of animals.
Coetzee
dramatizes the increasingly difficult relationships between the aging
novelist
Elizabeth Costello and her family and professional colleagues. She
progressively views her fellow human beings as criminals, while they
think that
she is demanding something of them-a radical change in the way they
treat animals-that
she has no right to demand, and that they have no obligation or desire
to
deliver. In the frame of fiction, Coetzee's story of Elizabeth
Costello's visit
to Appleton College contains empirical and philosophical arguments that
are
relevant to the ethical issue of how human beings should treat animals.
Unlike some
animals, human beings do not need to eat meat. We could-if only we
tried-treat
animals with due sympathy for their "sensation of being." In the
first of her lectures (the main part of Coetzee's first lecture),
Costello
concludes that there is no excuse for the lack of sympathy that human
beings display
toward other animals, because "there is no limit to the extent to which
we
can think ourselves into the being of another. There are no bounds to
the
sympathetic imagination." Yet most human beings do not stretch the
bounds
of our imaginations with regard to animals, because we "can do anything
[with regard to animals] and get away with it."
We have
closed our hearts to animals, Costello concludes, and our minds follow
our
hearts (or, more strictly speaking, our sympathies). Philosophy, she
argues, is
relatively powerless to lead, or in any event to lead in the right
direction,
because it lags our sympathies. This places the burden on something
other than our
rational faculties, to which philosophy typically appeals. Our
sympathetic
imaginations, she argues-to which poetry and fiction appeal more than
does
philosophy-should extend to other animals. The fictional form, in
Coetzee's
hands, therefore appears to have an ethical purpose: extending our
sympathies
to animals. If fiction does not so extend our sympathies, then neither
will
philosophy. If it does, then perhaps philosophy will follow.
Costello's
lectures within Coetzee's lectures therefore ask their audience to
"open
your heart and listen to what your heart says." Do animals
have rights? Do human beings have duties toward them regardless of
whether they
have rights? What kind of souls do animals have? What kind do we have?
Costello
does not answer these questions in her lectures, because they are too
philosophical
for the immediate task at hand. They presume that the mind can lead the
heart,
a presumption that Elizabeth Costello's experience has led her to
reject after
a long life of trying to convince other people of her perspective on
animals.
In any case, as Costello tells her audience at Appleton, "if you had
wanted someone to come here and discriminate for you between mortal and
immortal
souls, or between rights and duties, you would have called in a
philosopher,
not a person whose sole claim to your attention is to have written
stories
about made-up people."
Coetzee
stirs our imaginations by confronting us with an articulate,
intelligent,
aging, and increasingly alienated novelist who cannot help but be
exasperated
with her fellow human beings, many of them academics, who are
unnecessarily
cruel to animals and apparently (but not admittedly) committed to
cruelty. The story
urges us to re-conceive our devotion to reason as a universal value. Is
the
universe built upon reason? Is God a God of reason? If so, then "man is
godlike, animals thing-like." But Elizabeth Costello vehemently
dissents
from this anthropocentric perspective: "reason is neither the being of
the
universe nor the being of God. On the contrary, reason looks to me
suspiciously
like the being of human thought; worse than that, like the being of one
tendency
in human thought."
Does
Costello protest too much? Although she argues that philosophy is
totally
bankrupt in its ability to make our attitudes toward animals ethical,
Costello
also self-consciously employs philosophy in her lectures, often to
demonstrate
the weakness of those philosophical arguments that consider the lives
of non-reasoning
beings less valuable by virtue of their being less reasoning. "What is
so
special about the form of consciousness we recognize that makes killing
a
bearer of it a crime," she asks, "while killing an animal goes
unpunished?" Unlike philosophers, poets begin "with a feel for"
an animal's experience. That leads them to recognize the crime of
killing any
animal that can experience the sensation of being alive to the world.
Costello
urges us to recognize the accessibility of such sympathy for the
fullness of
animal being. "If we are capable of thinking our own death," she
asks, "why on earth should we not be capable of thinking our way into
the
life of a bat?"
What, then,
is the motivation for thinking our way into the lives of animals, if
not
morality? By her own account, however, Costello is motivated not by
moral
conviction but rather by "a desire to save my soul." She is not so
presumptuous as to think that she has succeeded in saving her soul,
although
she does treat her critics as if they had lost sight of their souls.
She
refuses to accept the compliments of the president of Appleton College,
who (in
an apparent attempt to defuse the mounting tension) says that he
admires her
way of life. In response, Costello points out that she wears leather
shoes and
carries a leather purse. "Surely one can draw a distinction between
eating
meat and wearing leather," the president offers in her defense.
"Degrees of obscenity," is Costello's uncompromising reply. The
president has succeeded only in increasing the tension. Costello
refuses to
take admiration for an answer. Her sensibilities and actions may be
superior to
those of her fellow human beings, but they remain nonetheless a source
of
internal agony.
Costello is self-aware. She anticipates her most
antagonistic critic
by saying that she knows "how talk of this kind polarizes people and
cheap
point-scoring only makes it worse." The kind of talk to which she
refers
is an analogy, which she draws again and again, between the way her
fellow
human beings treat animals and way the Third Reich treated Jews. "By
treating fellow human beings, beings created in the image of God, like
beasts," she says of the Nazis, "they had themselves become
beasts." She continues: "we are surrounded by an enterprise of
degradation, cruelty, and killing which rivals anything that the Third
Reich was
capable of .... "
The comparison with the Holocaust cannot go
unchallenged. In fact, the challenge to Costello is delivered not by a
philosopher
but by Costello's academic equal, an aging poet, Abraham Stern. Stern
refuses
to attend dinner with Costello not out of disrespect but because he is
deeply
affronted by her first lecture. Stern
delivers a letter telling Costello why he cannot break bread with her:
You took
over for your own purposes the familiar comparison between the murdered
Jews of
Europe and slaughtered cattle. The Jews died like cattle, therefore
cattle die
like Jews, you say. That is a trick with words which I will not accept.
You
misunderstand the nature of likenesses; I would even say you
misunderstand
willfully, to the point of blasphemy. Man is made in the likeness of
God but God does not
have the likeness of man. If Jews were treated like cattle, it does not
follow
that cattle are treated like Jews. The inversion insults the memory of
the
dead. It also trades on the horrors of the camps in a cheap way.
Just as
Stern is too offended by Costello's moral sensibilities to address her
in
person, so too Costello does not answer Stern's critique. Each is
offended by
the other's sensibilities, and they have little willingness or ability
or time
in their lives left to bridge the ethical and aesthetic divide between
them.
The Lives of Animals drives home how difficult
it can be
for morally serious people to sympathize with, or even understand, each
other's
perspectives. The distance between the two aging writers in the story,
Costello
and Stern, does not narrow as a consequence of their taking each other
seriously. Quite the contrary, at the end of her visit to Appleton (and
the end
of the story), Costello invokes the Holocaust analogy yet again.
Speaking to her
son about how radically disoriented she feels in this world, she
imagines going
into the bathroom of friends and seeing a soap-wrapper that says,
"Treblinka- 100% human stearate." Imagine
feeling this way about our fellow human beings who eat animals, yet
also seeing
human kindness in the very same people's eyes. "This is life. Everyone
else comes to terms with it," Costello reminds herself, "why can't
you? Why can't you?"
Should
Elizabeth Costello have come to terms with the way her family and
friends treat
animals, or should she have converted them-should she convert those of
us who
do not begin where she begins-to her position? Coetzee does not answer
these
questions for us. The story leaves us with a vivid sense of conflict
among
morally serious people over the mistreatment of animals and the
apparently
correlative conflict over analogizing that treatment to the most
heinous crimes
committed among human beings themselves. Central among the questions
Coetzee
leaves us with is whether there is any way-whether philosophical,
poetic, or
psychological-of resolving these ethical conflicts or reconciling these
competing sensibilities.
Four
prominent commentators-the literary theorist Marjorie Garber, the
philosopher
Peter Singer, the religious scholar Wendy Doniger, and the
primatologist Barbara
Smuts-discuss the form and content of Coetzee's lectures. Like previous
volumes
in the University Center for Human Values Series, The Lives of Animals draws
upon the insights of diverse disciplinary perspectives that too rarely
engage
with one another. Garber Singer, Doniger, and Smuts do not share a
single
academic discipline, nor are they even members of neighboring
disciplines but
their commentaries together help constitute a more complete
understanding of
how human beings can and should relate to animals.
At the same
time as she compares The Lives of
Animals to the academic novel, Marjorie
Garber highlights its distinctiveness. It is "suffused with pathos"
rather than the comedy that is typical of the academic novel. Its
analogies
pose "some of the most urgent ethical and political questions" of our
times. Garber questions the way in which serious analogy-as between
"the
murdered Jews of Europe and slaughtered cattle"-functions in fiction
and
literary criticism. She notes that although the appropriateness of the
Holocaust
analogy is hotly debated, it is regularly used, both obliquely and not
so
obliquely, as in the popular (and relatively uncontroversial)
children's film
Babe. Garber
explores the disadvantages as well as advantages of the ubiquitous
use of analogical arguments like these in literature. Fiction far more
than philosophy
has the "art of language" to offer, and that art is put to expert use
by Coetzee in his effort to provoke us to pursue an ethical issue that
would
not otherwise capture some people's attention or imagination. The Lives of
Animals is therefore, as Garber suggests, as much about the
value of literature
as it is about the lives of animals.
In a
commentary that is written in the form of a fictional dialogue between
an
animal rights philosopher and his daughter, Peter Singer, the most
eminent
philosophical defender of animal rights, imagines himself in the
unusual
position of confronting someone like Elizabeth Costello who is more
unconventional with regard to animals than even he is. "There is a more
radical egalitarianism about humans and animals running through her
lecture
than I would be prepared to defend," the philosopher says to his
daughter.
When his daughter takes Costello's side in the argument, the
philosopher
responds, "I feel, but I also think what I feel." The fact that human
beings think-think about their pain, their future, and their death-adds
value
to their lives, according to the philosopher. "The value that is lost
when
something is emptied depends on what was there when it was full, and
there is more
to human existence than there is to bat existence." The value that is
lost
in the killing of a human being is therefore greater than the value
lost in the
killing of a bat. It also follows for Singer's philosopher that to the
extent
that animals are "self-aware" and have "thoughts about things in
the future," there is "some reason for thinking it intrinsically
wrong to kill them-not absolutely wrong, but perhaps quite a serious
wrong."
Singer's
philosopher defends philosophy against Costello's attacks upon it. "We
can't take our feelings as moral data, immune from rational criticism,"
the philosopher says in response to his daughter's horror at his
suggesting
that their dog Max's life might not be intrinsically valuable. Painless
killing
of those animals who do not anticipate their death would not be in
itself morally
wrong, or at least not as heinous a crime as the painless killing of an
animal
who is self-conscious about life and death. If Singer's philosopher is
right,
then the morality of vegetarianism under circumstances where the
consumed
animals are painlessly killed can be distinguished from the morality of
compassionate treatment of animals.
Wendy
Doniger's commentary explores the distinction between practicing
vegetarianism
and being compassionate toward animals, a distinction that she suggests
is
implicit in many religious traditions. Different religions have
reasoned about
how to treat animals in seemingly contradictory ways. "The argument
that
humans (but not animals) are created in the image of god is often used
in the
West to justify cruelty to animals," Doniger points out, "but most
mythologies assume that animals, rather than humans, are the image of
God-which
may be a reason to eat them." Whereas in some religions, vegetarianism
is
connected to compassion for animals, in others it is more intimately
connected to
self-identity and the search for human salvation, as seems to be the
case with
Elizabeth Costello.
Barbara
Smuts, who has spent much of her professional life working and living
with
baboons and other animals, notices a "striking gap" in Coetzee's
text. Elizabeth Costello says little about "real-life [human] relations
with animals." As a primatologist, Smuts knows what it is like to live
with animals, but she speaks in her commentary less as a scientist than
as an
ordinary human being who likes to live with animals. "Entering
territory where,
perhaps, Costello (and maybe even Coetzee) feared to tread," Smuts
writes,
"I will attempt to close this gap, not through formal scientific
discourse,
but rather, as Elizabeth Costello urges, by speaking from the heart."
What
follows in Smuts' commentary is an account of the individuality of
animals who
befriend and are befriended by human beings. Smuts vividly presents a
narrative
case for regarding nonhuman beings as persons and for believing in
friendship
between human beings and animals. She revises as she reinforces
Elizabeth
Costello's claim that "there is no limit to the extent to which we can
think ourselves into the being of another."
In the pages
that follow, philosophers and poets, novelists and scientists, deans
and
presidents, parents, children, and friends all grapple with how human
beings
should treat animals and should treat one another in the midst of the
deep
disagreement that will no doubt continue
to brew over this issue for some time to come. Coetzee's
story ends with the ambiguously consoling words that Costello's son
voices to
his aging mother, "There, there, it will soon be over." By contrast,
these moral matters will not soon be over. They remain ever more
disconcerting,
in no small part owing to the words of Coetzee's characters.