|
What
Would Hannah Say?
Jeremy Waldron
Reflections
on
Literature and Culture
by Hannah
Arendt,
edited and
with an
introduction by Susannah
Young-ah
Gottlieb.
Stanford
University
Press,
360 pp.,
$65.00;
$24.95 (paper)
The
Jewish
Writings
by Hannah
Arendt,
edited by Jerome Kohn
and Ron
H. Feldman.
Schocken,
624 pp.,
$35.00
Essays
in
Understanding, 1930-1954:
Formation,
Exile, and
Totalitarianism
by Hannah
Arendt,
edited and
with an
introduction by Jerome
Kohn.
Schocken,
458 pp.,
$16.95 (paper)
The Origins
of
Totalitarianism
by Hannah
Arendt,
with an
introduction by Samantha
Power.
Schocken,
674 pp.,
$35.00
Why Arendt
Matters
by
Elisabeth
Young-Bruehl.
Yale
University
Press, 232 pp., $22.00
1.
Hannah
Arendt was born in Lower Saxony
on October 14,1906. She grew up in Konigsberg
and studied philosophy with Martin Heidegger and Karl Jaspers. In the
early
1930s, she lived in Berlin
and worked for a German Zionist organization, collecting evidence for
publication abroad about anti-Semitism in German society. She also
helped run a
sort of "underground railroad," getting political enemies of the new
Hitler regime (mostly Communists) out of the country. In 1933, after
having
been arrested in Berlin and
held briefly for a few days by the police, she fled
without papers but with her widowed mother to Prague,
then Geneva, and then Paris.
In Paris,
she worked for an organization helping
young Jews who wanted to
settle in Palestine.
(Arendt herself visited Jerusalem in 1935.) In 1940, like
most German refugees, she was like most German
refugees, she was interned
in a camp, from which she escaped in the chaos
following the fall of
France.
Before the Vichy government began
handing over
Jews for deportation to Germany,
Arendt secured a visa to enter the United
States,
and traveled by train to Lisbon and
thence to New York.
In New
York,
she wrote for the German-language newspaper Aufbau on issues
related to the fate of the Jews in Europe.
Many of her columns are reproduced in a remarkable collection. The
Jewish
Writings, just published. Arendt was one of a small group of refugees
agitating
for the establishment of a specifically Jewish army "to join the battle
against Hitler as Jews, in Jewish battle formations under a Jewish
flag."
And she was involved from an early stage in various controversies
surrounding
the question of Palestine,
arguing for arrangements that would take full account of the need for
Arab-Jewish cooperation.
After
seventeen years of statelessness, she was naturalized
as an American citizen in 1950.
Arendt lived through
very dark times, some of the darkest ever seen in Europe,
and in the period from the mid-1940s to the mid-1960s, she immersed
herself in
an attempt to understand the murderous horror that had revealed itself.
The
Origins of Totalitarianism and Eichmann in Jerusalem were the great and
controversial
products of that attempt at understanding.
For
her, the years of total war and the murder of millions
of Jews told us not just what Nazis were capable of but what human
beings were
capable of. It was not enough, she wrote, to say "God be thanked, I am
not
like that" in the face of what we had learned of the potentialities in
the
German national character. "Rather, in fear and trembling," she said,
"have [we] finally realized of what man is capable."
Arendt lived
through
difficult times in the United States too. She
taught at Berkeley,
at the New School,
and at the University
of Chicago during
periods
of serious campus unrest and racial disturbance. The essays she wrote
in the
1960s (many of them in The New York Review), which she published in a
book
called Crises of the Republic, bore witness to the catastrophic effect
on
American politics of a disastrous war in Southeast Asia and the
normalization
of lying and the wishful thinking that was necessary to sustain it. She
commented with bitter irony on the new world that was
coming into existence in the 1950s and 1960s—its "horrid
shallowness," a pervasive thoughtlessness and a panic stricken drift
from
one vision to another not unlike the fear and restlessness that
prepared
Europeans for fascism in the 1920s and was making Americans ready for
God knows
what horrors in the future.
2.
She died
in 1975. In
the outpouring of conferences and volumes in 2006 celebrating the
hundredth
anniversary of her birth, Arendt scholars have reminded us that we too
live in
dark times, and a theme of many of the lectures that have been given,
the symposiums
that have been put together, and the new introductions that have been
stapled
onto old works to celebrate her birthday has been to ask what Arendt
would do
and what Arendt would
think and say about the dark times we live in at the
beginning of the twenty-first century.
Like her, we
are
confronted with criminality in government and lying by state officials
as a
matter of principle. Like her, we have seen the subversion of the
Constitution,
abuse of the rule of law, and a disastrous war in which, facing
"outright,
humiliating defeat,"
the
only imperative is to find modes of withdrawal that will
somehow not count as "losing"—as though, as she said during the
Vietnam War, "'the greatest power on earth' lacked the inner strength
to
live with defeat.' (1) True, we have our own nightmares to add:
stolen elections, contempt for international
institutions, liberal Islamophobia, the use and defense of torture, and
the
concentration of prisoners regarded as threats to America
in
camps where they languish indefinitely beyond the reach
of the law.
It's our own
mess,
but it's a propitious time to celebrate Hannah Arendt's birthday. For
perhaps
her life and her writings have lessons for us. Maybe Arendt can be
enlisted
posthumously as an ally, so that (changing a few names) we can make her
denunciations our denunciations, her despair a motif for our own
lamentations,
her insights a lantern in our darkness.
Certainly
a lot of what she wrote is pertinent to the
horrors of our time. She wrote about terror: The Origins of
Totalitarianism
contains a remarkable phenomenological account of the "bestial
desperate
terror" that characterized life in the camps and paralyzed thought in a
totalitarian
society. She also wrote about terrorism and she was uncompromising in
her
attacks on Jewish terrorism in Palestine
in the 1940s: "They think it is all right to murder anyone who can be
murdered —an innocent English Tommy or a
harmless Arab
in the market of Haifa."
Although she died
well before the phrase "war on terror" was conceived, there is much
to learn from some of the things she says about the abuses of state
power in
this regard. For example, she was peremptory in her condemnation of
Israeli
raids on Arab settlements in the 1950s: "The shortest statement to be
made
would be: Thou shalt not kill, not even Arab women and children." (2). Elisabeth Young-Bruehl thinks Arendt would
have condemned Bush's modern war on terror as inherently unlimited and
she
would have worried about the possibility of a duplicate government
emerging
under the auspices of the
homeland security state, shadowing the constitutional government but
secret and
free of legal constraint. Arendt was alarmed at the prospect that the
worldwide
network of states might leave certain persons—stateless and
homeless—beyond the
reach of any law. She knew about internment camps. She would have been
appalled
by the "legal black hole" at Guantanamo Bay.
She wrote bitterly about places where "the inmates, even if they happen
to
keep alive, are more effectively cut off from the world of the living
than if
they had died."
Most important, Arendt understood the
insidious and non
spectacular aspects of political and moral deterioration. It is here,
if at
all, that her concept of "the banality of evil" comes into its own.
Long before the final descent into terror and murder, the Nazis engaged
in
low-level intimidation to compel "coordination" with their regime on
the part of various sectors of society—university academics being one.
Such
coordination did not necessarily mean that Germans had to embrace
Nazism, as
Arendt's mentor Martin Heidegger did when he became rector at Freiburg University.
Scholars and public figures would convince one another that the
"realities" had changed and that anyone who did not wish to be
regarded as naïve should begin rearranging their ideas. This we have
seen
recently in America,
as intellectuals, journalists, and public figures scramble to condemn
one another
for lacking a sense of "realism" appropriate for a post-September 11
world.
So there is plenty
of room for parallels between Arendt's times and our times, between her
public
comments and laments and the things that we might say now or ought to
say. The assistance
that Arendt might be able to offer us for 2007 is the theme of a new
book—Why
Arendt Matters—by her former student and biographer Elisabeth
Young-Bruehl.
Brief and lucidly written, it is a good account of some of the more
difficult aspects of her work. But as the
title suggests
it is organized around the immediate need for illumination:
Recently,
as our world has grown
darker, as America—the nation Arendt
admired before all others, her home after twelve years of being a
stateless
refugee—has grown further and further removed from its founding
principles,
which all concerned respect for the public realm, I have frequently
found
myself wondering: What would Arendt have said? What would she think of
this
world we live in, three decades after her death?
In a new
preface to her biography of Arendt, Young-Bruehl
reminds us that Arendt published a book of essays in 1968 called Men in
Dark
Times- essays about people "like Walter Benjamin, Karl Jaspers, and
Pope
John XXIII. Arendt wrote there that we have a right to expect some
illumination
... from the uncertain, flickering, and often weak light that some men
and
women, in their lives and works, will kindle under almost all
circumstances and
shed over the time span that was given them on earth. (3)
Should we
not look
for this light in Arendt's life and work, as she looked for light in
her own
dark times to the life and work of others?
3.
I should say right away that I am very
skeptical about this
expectation, and for many reasons—some of them specific to Arendt, some
of them
more general about any such question: "What would the Framers do?"
"What would Leo Strauss do?" "What would Jesus do?" I think that if we
understand why such
questions are inappropriate, we will have a better grasp of the
significance
and the limitations of Arendt's writings than if we treat them as a
source of
sibyllic inspiration.
To begin, there
are plenty of people who will recoil from the search for illumination
because
they don't trust Arendt's writings and never did. The controversy over
Eichmann
in Jerusalem
still festers and there are those who regard the missteps of that book
as
typical of a more pervasive lack of political judgment on Arendt's
part. Some of this criticism
is silly and malicious and hasn't been challenged as strongly as it
should be.
Walter Laqueur attributed Arendt's alleged misjudgments about Israel
and things
Jewish to the fact that "she had read too much anti-Semitic literature
for
her own good" and her misjudgments about the United States to the fact
that like most of her fellow emigrés, she never learned to drive a car.
(4)
Among
Anglo-American
analytic philosophers, Arendt's work is neither widely read nor
respected.
(Arendt returned the compliment. Though she had been trained in
philosophy, she
insisted she was a political theorist, not a political philosopher.
Citing the
ancient prejudice of philosophy against politics, she told an
interviewer in
1964, "I have said good-bye to philosophy once and for all." (5)
Political theorists, for their part, are hardly unanimous in their
enthusiasm
for her work. Isaiah Berlin
disliked her. He spoke of "the egregious Hannah Arendt" and, though
neither
the most rigorous nor the most consecutive thinker himself, he made a
pronouncement to the effect that she produces no arguments, no evidence
of serious philosophical or historical thought. It is all a stream of
metaphysical free association. She moves from one sentence to another,
without
logical connection, without either rational or imaginative links
between them. (6)
This
is
also very
silly. It is true that Arendt's writings exhibit neither the desiccated
algebra
of logical analysis nor the chipper moral commentary of the journal
Philosophy
and Public Affairs. Much of her writing is impressionistic and combines
theory
with history. (In fact, it's not much different from Berlin's.) Her
style recalls Tocqueville
more than it does John Rawls, and it is none the worse for that. It is
true
that her prose can have a portentous and stricken tone. That is partly
the result of
the subjects she is addressing. But it has to be said: the style
associated
with Arendt can be irritating, if not in her writings then in those of
her
followers, who find it hard to resist the temptation to echo her
bitterness as
they lay out the ironies of her thought. It is very wearying. Solemnity
for the
subject matter becomes a sort of reverence that speakers
self-consciously
summon up at hushed conferences devoted to her memory. No one makes
light of
Hannah Arendt.
4.
"What would Hannah do?" An oracular
interpretation
can cheapen her work and distract us from its importance. Samantha
Power—author of "A Problem from Hell"
(2002), a remarkable study of
modern genocide— has written the introduction for a new edition of The
Origins
of Totalitarianism. In it she writes that Arendt's masterwork is
important not
just for historical understanding but as "wisdom for today's dark
times—wisdom that we ignore at our peril." The lessons apparently
consist
in such statements as these:
Origins shows that
Arendt would not be satisfied with a policy that aimed to violently
quash
today's threat without seeking to
understand
it.
Now, actually this
is the opposite of what Arendt said. She
said that:
we
cannot delay our
fight against totalitarianism until we have "understood" it, because
we do not, and cannot expect to understand it definitively as
long as it has
not definitively been defeated.
Maybe things are
different in the war on terror, but, if so, it is not Arendt from whom
we have
learned that they are different. I suspect
that anyone who has studied The Origins of Totalitarianism, anyone who
is
familiar with its dense learning, the scale of its analysis, its huge
speculative leaps, its risks and dangers, will have a sense that some
thing is wrong
with this sort of extrapolation. Power's introduction and
Young-Bruehl's
treatment of the book as a "field manual" for our times have the
effect of making it into an icon, rather than a
work of
historical analysis—history close-up, as Hans Morgenthau observed—worth
grappling
with and criticizing on its own ground. Here's a very minor instance of
what I
mean. The first edition of Origins had a plain green and brown dust jacket, with the
title and the author's name. Subsequent editions have had a slightly
more
complicated pattern, and one recent edition presents a cover panel
filled with
an array of young Nazis giving the Hitler salute. That makes sense. The
jacket
of the latest edition, however, the 2004 edition with Samantha
Power's introduction, is just a photograph of Arendt, as though the
book were
about her, not about the origins of the horror that Europe
witnessed in mid century. Almost all the new editions and the new books
by or about her have her photograph on the front of
the dust jacket. This was never true of her books when she was alive,
and it
seems inappropriate for someone who spoke emphatically of her
unwillingness to
appear for public celebration. (7)
5.
"What would
Arendt think?" A third reason for suspecting the question arises from
the
fact that her writing was full of hard sayings—willful, cranky,
provocative.
The slightest acquaintance with Arendt's work indicates that if she
were among
us we should expect to hear much that is disconcerting, certainly more
searching and controversial than the liberal dinner party consensus
that we are
comfortable with. Her reflections on the Eichmann trial are the most
notorious
example of this—particularly her comments on the docile cooperation of
some Jewish authorities in the
Holocaust. The new volume of Jewish Writings shows that some of what
she said
in 1963 was consonant with more affirmative themes in her columns
during World
War II. I have already mentioned her call for a Jewish army. In one
piece
written in August 1944, she refers to an AP report of young Jewish
girls, submachine guns over their shoulders, marching proudly through
the
streets of Vilna after its liberation. One of them, a eventeen-year-old
named
Betty, said he had killed six Germans:
"A German came
and took my family to the ghetto. That's how defenseless and docile we
were in
1941. "... She is ashamed even to think of how
one single German could with
impunity lead sixty Jews into slavery and presumably death. With six shots she
expunged the shame of those
victims.... I
am greatly afraid [said Arendt] that
peace will teach Betty a second cruel lesson.... She does not yet know that we actually
glory only in being victims,
innocent victims, and that we celebrate her and
those like her not as heroes but as martyrs.
Arendt wrote then as she wrote
throughout
her life in a way that was uncontaminated by any fear of offending or
by any
sense that "this might note the time" to say what she wanted to say.
Another case in point
is her essay on the desegregation of schools in the American
South—"Reflections on Little
Rock,"
published in Dissent in 1959. (8).
The discomfort here is that her observations did not unambiguously like
the
side of the desegregation movement. Ever a federalist, she spoke
ingenuously in favor
of states' rights though she must also have known such talk was code
for
segregation. She said that forcing parents to send their children
to integrated schools, where they risked violence and rejection, meant
depriving parents of the right to control their children and the right
to free
association. The education and upbringing of children, she said, were
private
matters, not public.
This
was a view one
could understand better if one had read her meditation on the
phenomenology of
the public and private, published a year earlier in The Human Condition. Otherwise
it would have struck some of her readers in Dissent as preposterous. She attacked the
idealists who said that the color of one's skin should be simply
ignored in
public and social life: "To argue that they are merely exterior
appearances is to beg the question. For it is precisely appearances
that
'appear' in public"—as opposed to "inner qualities, gifts of heart or
mind."
I
don't cite these passages in order to join those who have denounced the
essay.
It is in fact an insightful as well as a provocative statement. The
point is
that it is utterly unpredictable. And I suspect it was written from the
depths
of Arendt's own convictions and experience. When she wrote that "the
very
attempt to start desegregation in education and in schools had...
unfairly
shifted the burden of responsibility from the shoulders of adults to
those of
children," we could recall what she said about her own school days in
Konigsberg:
When my teachers
made anti Semitic remarks—mostly not about
me, but
about other Jewish girls, eastern Jewish
students in particular— I was told to get up
immediately, leave the classroom,
come home, and report everything exactly. Then
my
mother wrote one of her many registered
letters; and
for me the matter was
completely settled. I had a day off
from school, and that was
marvelous! But when it came from
children, I was not
permitted to
tell
about it at home. That
didn't count. You defended yourself
against what came from children.
There
are other
views of hers that might sit uncomfortably with the sentiments we
should expect
to find support for, when we ask what Hannah would say. One of our
concerns has
been the Bush administration's contempt for international law and
international
institutions. We worry—as an aspect of our dark
times—that the US has
become unilateralist, that it has turned its back on
global cooperation. Should we expect the ghost of Arendt to endorse our
outrage
at this? I don't know. Samantha Power writes in her introduction to The
Origins
of Totalitarianism of the "false promise of liberal
internationalism." Arendt was suspicious of international institutions.
I
think she might have had grave doubts about the workings of the United
Nations
during the months before the American invasion of Iraq.
She might have been wrong about that. But why does it
matter? Why not form our own judgment on the issue even if it can't be
projected onto her? Young-Bruehl
acknowledges that reckoning what Arendt would say is a presumptuous
enterprise
for it involves trying to guess what her "fiercely observant eyes"
would see, what her original and famously contrary mind would want to emphasize. Arendt wanted to understand
the unprecedented. She insisted on this at the very beginning of The Origins of
Totalitarianism:
Comprehension
does
not mean ... deducing the
unprecedented from precedents, or
explaining phenomena by such
analogies
and generalities that the impact of
reality
and the shock of experience are no longer
felt.... Comprehension ... means the unpremeditated, attentive facing
up to,
and resisting of, reality—whatever it may be. (9)
Young-Bruehl
is
surely right that Arendt would be appalled by the lazy analogical
thinking that
equates September 11 with Pearl Harbor,
or Bush
with Churchill, or every decision to pursue diplomacy with a repetition
of Neville
Chamberlain's policy of appeasement. But we can't just leave it there.
If we
take her focus on the unprecedented seriously, we must pursue our own
pathways of
thought and judgment in grappling with our situation. I don't mean
there
is nothing to be learned from Arendt's books; quite the contrary. But
there's
probably nothing to be learned by a method that involves asking what
her books are saying to us now.
6.
Arendt was asked once what she told her students to do during the events of the 1960s and 1970s. She dismissed the
question angrily: "My God! These are
adults! We are not in the nursery!" (10)
The
worst thing
about the question "What would
Hannah do?" is the likelihood that it—or the cult that generates it—becomes a substitute for thinking for
ourselves. The nature of thinking is one
of the most important concerns of Arendt's social and political theory.
Thinking is the "habit of
examining
whatever happens to come to pass or to attract
attention" in inner dialogue, in a sort of conversation with oneself, where every mental reaction is subject to
criticism and in which the inner critic is also held to answer back and
forth.
Arendt
speculated
that, in many circumstances, moral conduct seems to depend on this
"intercourse of man with himself.' (11). A person contemplates murder,
for
example, but says to him or herself: "I can't do this. If I did, I
would
have to live with a murderer for the rest
of my
life." But thinking is also one of the most fragile features of human
consciousness. Part of what Arendt meant by the banality of evil is the
possibility of wrongdoing that opens up when this inner dialogue is no
longer
an important feature of people's lives, so that the prospect of who I
would
have to live with in myself is no longer a
concern.
Thinking
is
possible, she says, among people who know how to talk back and forth
with one
another— that's how one learns to think. But thinking will atrophy in
an
environment that lacks the stillness that allows us to concentrate in
inner
dialogue or, more ominously, in a social environment where distrust
among
people makes first outer conversation, then inner conversation
impossible. We know
that in totalitarian societies, distrust is fostered deliberately to
this end.
It is a question for us whether something less malign but equally
consequential
may be happening in the noise and superficiality of modern consumer
society.
Once again, Arendt
reserves special venom for intellectuals who have forgotten how to
think:
This new class of
intellectuals who, as literati and
bureaucrats, as scholars and scientists,
no less than as critics and providers of
entertainment ... have proved more than once in
recent times
that they are more susceptible to
whatever happens to be public opinion and less
capable of judging for themselves than almost any
other social group.
The paraphernalia of thoughtlessness
is legion. Clichés and
jargon, stock phrases and analogies, dogmatic adherence to established
bodies
of theory and ideology, the petrification of ideas— these are all
devices
designed to relieve the mind of the burden of thought, while
maintaining an impression of intellectual
cultivation. Could the question "What would Hannah think?" become a
device of this sort? I very much fear
that it might, and that we have to find
ways of engaging with her work that do
not contribute to this danger.
I
don't at all mean
to deny that Schocken and other
publishing houses have done us a favor in putting all this
material in front of us. The Arendt books
that have been published over the last
year or so are valuable models of genuinely original thinking, and her
columns
and essays contain remarkable insight. Some are literary, not
political.
Reflections on Literature and Culture contains fascinating essays on Kafka, Proust, and Brecht. There are
meditations on the novels of Hermann Broch {The Death of Virgil) and
the poetry
of Randall Jarrell ("He taught me the specific gravity of English
words,
whose relative weight, as in all languages, is ultimately determined by
poetic
usage"). The earliest piece in the collection is a discussion of
Rilke's
poetry from 1930, the last a brief tribute to Auden, published in The
New Yorker
just months before Arendt died.
The
pieces in some
of the other books—particularly Essays in Understanding—deal more
politically
with the unfolding of events, but they are so engaged with time and
place that we can barely
recall the references. Who thinks now that the British
Commonwealth could
have fostered
a Jewish-Arab Palestine after the
war? (Arendt did, in
1945.12) Who now worries that ex-Communists bring a totalitarian
mentality to
the denunciation of their own comrades
and have nothing affirmative to offer but a fanatical idealization of
American
foreign policy? (Arendt did, in 1953. She wrote that their activities
"almost always result in showing mistrust among citizens whose 'friendship,' philia, according to Aristotle,
is the surest foundation of political life.")
Reading
these
columns, it is just possible that we will learn something about how to
respond
to events—step back, look behind the slogans, listen to the other side,
be
aware on either side that you may be being lied to. But we will
certainly not
learn what our response should be. The tribute that is owed to the
particularity of Arendt's work is not imitation and it is not the
application
of some lessons we are supposed to have learned; it is our own resolve
to think
things through here and now, as she thought about them there and then. +
(1) Hannah Arendt, "Home to Roost" (1975), in Responsibility and
Judgment, edited by Jerome Kohn (Schocken, 2003) p.
269.
(2) Hannah Arendt, quoted in Elisabeth
Young-Bruehl, Hannah Arendt: For
Love of the World, second edition, (Yale University Press,
2004) p. 291.
(3) Hannah Arendt: Men in Dark Times
(Harvest, 1970) p. ix(4) Walter Laqueur, "The Arendt Cult:
Hannah Arendt as
Political Commentator", Journal of Contemporary History, Vol 33, No. 4
(October 1998).
(5) Hannah Arendt: '"What Remains?- The Language remains': A
Conversation with Gunter Gauss, in Essays in Understanding, p.2
(6) Isaiah Berlin and Ramin Jahanbegloo, Conversation with Isaiah
Berlin (Scriber, 1991) p. 82.
(7) See Hannah Arendt, "Prologue", in Responsability and Judgment, pp.
11-12.
(8) Included in Responsibility and Judgment pp. 193-213.
(9) Hannah Arendt, preface to the first edition of The Origins
of
Totalitarianism (p. xxvi of the 2004 edition).
(10) Hannah Arendt, "On Hannah Arendt," in Hannah Arendt: The recovery
of the Public World, edited by Melvyn Hill (St. Martin's, 1979), p. 310.
(11) Arendt, Responsability and Judgment, p.67.
(12) "Hannah Arendt, The Jewish Writings, p. 196. It's interesting that
Isaiah Berlin, too, toyed with
a similar possibility:
If the British
Commonwealth had put its umbrella over
the new State [in 1945]—would the Arab States have attacked a victorious
Britain?
Would the Irgun have attempted a civil
war, and would not Ben-Gurion have
averted it?
Might not such a
development have saved much blood,
prevented
much bitterness and, above all, the
conditions of beleaguerment in which the State of Israel
has led its entire existence?
See "Zionist Politics in Wartime Washington: A Fragment
of Personal Reminiscence," in Isaiah Berlin, Letters, 1928-1946, edited
by Henry
Hardy (Cambridge University Press,
2004), p.691.
|