A
college student working on a seminar paper about the mechanics of the
Rwandan genocide of 1994 sees his father reading “Black Earth” (Tim Duggan/Crown),
the Yale historian Timothy Snyder’s new book on the Holocaust, and asks
the unaskable question: Do we really need one more book on the
Holocaust? The facts are in and clear, he says, while so many other
human horrors demand our historical understanding and get so much less:
how many new books have been published this year on the Belgian genocide
in the Congo? Doesn’t endlessly retelling the story of the murder of
the Jews of Europe let us give ourselves the appearance of moral
seriousness while immunizing us to the urgencies of actual moral
seriousness? Piety is the opposite of compassion, which is better
directed toward those who need it now than toward those who were denied
it then.
The student turns away in
exasperation before his father can reply that Snyder has framed this
book in order to respond to that question. It’s why he has given it the
subtitle “The Holocaust as History and Warning.” Snyder’s point is that
if we really understood what happened in Ukraine in 1941 we would begin
to understand what happened in Rwanda in 1994—and might prevent
something like it from happening elsewhere next year. He even argues,
against the grain of the usual historian’s practice, that there are
recurrent patterns in history and that the bad ones can be identified
and perhaps undone.
Though
Snyder’s goal is to clarify history, he is certain (and here he is like
most academic historians) that one can clarify history only by
complicating it. As one might expect, an extremely complicated story,
formed in the field of Holocaust studies, trails his new effort. His
previous book, “Bloodlands,” was an effort to historicize the
Holocaust—to remove it from the stock black-and-white imagery,
accompanied by minor-key cello music, in which it had come to reside, at
least within the popular imagination. In particular, he sought to
re-center our attention on the “forgotten” Holocaust, on the reality
that at least as many Jews were killed in mass actions in Ukraine,
Poland, Belarus, and the Baltic states as were dispatched in the death
factories of Birkenau and Treblinka. Soldiers machine-gunning people on
the edge of a pit that they’d dug themselves and that already held the
bodies of their families—that was the true image of the Holocaust, more
so than trains running on time to industrialized gassings and burnings.
Auschwitz, in this view, is, to put it brutally, almost a tourist trap
for historians. What distinguished the horror from other horrors was not
lists on graph paper and bureaucratic requisitions for Zyklon B gas. It
was a soldier writing home to his wife about killing Jewish babies in
Belarus: “During the first try, my hand trembled a bit as I shot, but
one gets used to it. By the tenth try I aimed calmly and shot surely at
the many women, children, and infants. . . . Infants flew in great arcs
through the air, and we shot them to pieces in flight.
Historicizing
anything risks diminishing it—history, after all, is what used to
happen—and critics complained that Snyder, by robbing the horror of its
industrial modernity, had made it a folkloric and merely regional
tragedy. Worse, they complained, by blending the crimes of the war with
Soviet crimes that began in the thirties—the Ukrainian famine, for
instance—he was explaining away the enthusiastic participation in the
mass killing of Jews by the locals, Ukrainians and Poles in particular.
Instead of seeing crazed German fanatics who communicated their pathogen
to hardened Jew-haters, he asked us to see what happened in the forties
as a blind scything through a harsh landscape, ignorant armies clashing
by night and killing millions in the darkness, a scene from Bosch more
than from Kafka. “Mass violence of a sort never before seen in history
was visited upon this region,” he wrote in “Bloodlands.” “The victims
were chiefly Jews, Belarusans, Ukrainians, Poles, Russians, and Balts,
the peoples native to these lands.” By making the massacres part of a
geographic tragedy of invasion and counterinvasion, and of victimized
native populations who suffered in various ways along with the Jews,
Snyder could be accused of playing down the role of ideological and
indigenous anti-Semitism. “The gesture of a finger across the throat,
remembered with loathing by a few Jewish survivors,” Snyder wrote with
great delicacy, “was meant to communicate to the Jews that they were
going to die—though not necessarily that the Poles wished this upon
them.” It is certainly not the way that Claude Lanzmann’s “Shoah”
represents the gesture. Elsewhere, Snyder wrote that the “victims of
Auschwitz were more likely to be bourgeois and thus suitable targets of
comfortable identification,” although “comfortable” is surely the last
feeling anyone reading about their suffering would ever have. By
treating Slavs, Balts, and Jews all as victims together, his critics
claim, he was obscuring a tragic core truth. Slavs and Balts died along
with Jews, but Slavs and Balts killed Jews as well, in a way that Jews
did not kill Slavs and Balts
Snyder
maintains that too much emphasis has been placed on the ferocity of
indigenous anti-Semitism; that it was instead the destruction of Eastern
European states by the Nazis, and then the skillful “political”
exploitation of their wretched recent history, which made their lands
into killing grounds and a small number of their people into
executioners. Without the state apparatus that had long accepted,
however grudgingly, ethnic coexistence, and with the murder of Jews made
into a sign of renunciation of “Judeobolshevism,” intolerable pressure
was placed on the native population. He points out that, while the Jews
of Estonia died almost to a man, the Jews of Denmark largely survived,
and that this was not because Estonians hated Jews and Danes did not but
because the Estonian state—though it had had only the briefest of
existences before—was destroyed, and the Danish one left mostly intact
Snyder’s
new book is meant, in part, to respond to the criticisms of
“Bloodlands,” and a reader familiar with the controversies will note in
the text more sublimated anger than might at first appear. Angry
authors, even when their books are not explicit replies, end up
incorporating unsent responses into the web of the text, where the angry
red threads stand out. If the complaint about “Bloodlands” was that
Snyder made the Holocaust a local event, this book is meant to
universalize it again, with the understanding that what is universal in
human experience is what is local and political.
Why do
we need any new books on the extermination of the Jews? The Shoah, it
seems, has come to be read for portents and interpretation as much as
for history itself. Yet one reason that the small scholarly details
matter is that they provide an arsenal for whatever argument you want to
make about the present. If you believe that the mass extermination of
the Jews was already implicit in the orders given for the June, 1941
invasion of Russia, then you are likely to see it as proceeding
according to a long-standing fixed plan of Hitler’s; if you believe that
the Final Solution, properly so called, was a panicky, confused
improvisation arrived at in December, 1941, after the German failure at
Moscow and the Russian counterattack, then you will probably see it as a
response made by a mostly disordered and dysfunctional evil. If June,
you are likely to believe that bad people do what they say they will; if
December, you believe that the worst things happen when bad people get
cornered by their own bad behavior. How you feel about things as
seemingly remote as Iranian deals and Putin’s aggressions is shaped
by—or shapes—your judgment of the historical micro-details.
More
broadly, if you believe, with Snyder, that the Second World War was
really about subject peoples robbed of their states and their identity
at a moment of environmental crisis and pitted against one another by a
brutal colonialism, you are likely to see in Rwanda a similar kind of
tragedy, as Snyder does—and you are likely to be sympathetic, as Snyder
is, to protecting small-state identities and encouraging their
nationalisms. If, with the Israeli historian Alon Confino, whose recent
“A World Without Jews” is written in quiet opposition to Snyder’s views,
you see in the Shoah the vengeance of atavistic tribalism on liberal
modernity, you are likely to worry about all incantations of
authenticity. Far from being sympathetic to revived nationalisms as
bulwarks of the oppressed, you are likely to be suspicious of them
(possibly even extending to the renascent Jewish kind).
Snyder
begins the new book with an unorthodox and provocative account of
Hitler’s thinking. He stresses two arresting elements: Hitler’s
skepticism about using agricultural science for increased food
production and (usefully discomfiting for an American readership) his
dependence on an American model of development. Hitler, Snyder tells us,
was obsessed with the question of growing enough grain to feed the
German population and, for various crackpot reasons, didn’t believe that
modern agronomy could make it happen on native soil. He saw himself
doing in Eastern Europe, and in Ukraine especially, what Americans had
done in the Great Plains: extinguish or exile the natives while taking
over the land to feed the metropolis. Lebensraum meant “living
space,” but in a different sense from the way we normally understand it:
a place to grow grain rather than a place to put Germans
Snyder’s
Hitler was not exactly convinced that the Germans were a superior race.
He was convinced that they might become a superior race, given their
bloodlines and their numbers, but they would have to prove it in
competition with other races on the world stage. Startling as it is,
this view explains many aspects of Hitler’s character: his physical
distance from the ideal he espoused (they aren’t like me, but I will
midwife a superior race that I do not belong to); his unappeasable
appetite for war; his rage at his compatriots for losing his war; his
readiness, at the end, to see German land destroyed, German cities
burned, German women raped—his manifest desire for a bonfire of the
Germans. He had given them every chance to show themselves a superior
race, and, since they had failed the test of history, they must suffer
the consequences.
Snyder’s Hitler is
no doubt made more neatly uniform in purpose than he really was.
Revolutionary ideas tend to be rigorous: if you are plotting a socialist
utopia, a blueprint, however unreal, is called for. Reactionary ideas,
forged in rage, tend to be emotive and incoherent. We miss their appeal
if we search them for regularities they don’t possess. It takes a
purpose to illuminate a plan; it takes only one high passion to set fire
to many more
As
Snyder moves toward the specifics of the German invasion of the Soviet
Union, in 1941, he reveals again that, while no apologist for the
indigenous murderers, he is, certainly, a partisan of the peoples of
Eastern Europe. He hates the way that the Ukrainians, the Latvians, and
the Poles have been made into peasant demons, with Western sages nodding
and saying, well, the Nazis “unleashed the old hatreds.” He writes:
It
is tempting to imagine that a simple idea in the minds of simple people
decades past and thousands of miles away can explain a complex event.
The notion that local east European antisemitism killed the Jews of
eastern Europe confers upon others a sense of superiority akin to that
the Nazis once felt. These people are quite primitive, we can allow
ourselves to think. Not only does this account fail as an explanation of
the Holocaust; its racism prevents us from considering the possibility
that not only Germans and Jews but also local peoples were individual
human agents with complex goals that were reflected in politics.
Ukrainians
may have massacred their Jewish neighbors. But this was not because the
Ukrainians had always hated Jews; it was because the famine of the
thirties had led the Ukrainian people to fear Soviet power, and the Nazi
invocation of Judeobolshevism as the cause of their miseries provided a
pat and plausible enemy. (The Soviet administration did employ Jews
“disproportionately to their numbers,” Snyder observes, although most
Soviet collaborators weren’t Jewish.) Some did terrible things, but they
did them out of political desperation and misrouted nationalism, not
enduring hate.
Snyder’s regular
invocation of “politics” is meant to illuminate this devil’s dance of
impossibilities. The local Slavs or Baltic peoples, having previously
collaborated with the Communists, could reclaim their national
inheritance by murdering Jews, and cleansing themselves of the stain of
collaboration. Neat trick. By supplanting “ancient hatreds” with
contemporary politics, Snyder wants to situate the massacres within the
specific logic of a time and place. Ukrainians and Polish Catholics
don’t just hate Jews and kill them any chance they get. You have to put
them in extremis first. The local populations got caught up in the
killing because it was the prudent thing to do, given the context of the
occupation.
Yet if the concept of
“politics” is to be explanatory it should show how power gets dispersed
and rebalanced among contending groups. Politics is how people adjust to
one another’s needs and potential for violence. In the circumstance
where one party has all the power, though, the invocation of politics
seems unhelpful. The politics of a slaughterhouse is not really
politics, at least not to the pigs; it is just a division of the labor.
To coöperate or not is a political choice, made every day in prisons; to
obey or die is not.
The real end
of Snyder’s relentless invocation of “politics” is, one comes to feel,
not without its politics. Snyder does not want the Putinists of 2015 to
be able to discredit Ukrainian nationalism by pointing to Ukrainian
participation in the Holocaust: he wants to make it clear that the
Ukrainian nationalists were, in the hackneyed phrase, “victims, too.”
But they were victims of a peculiar kind, and one can cheer their
emancipation today without looking past their history. Snyder asks us
not to blame the Lithuanians and the Latvians for what they did to the
Jews without first blaming the Soviets for what they did to the
Lithuanians and the Latvians. Surely one can blame all the evil actors
without having to take sides with any. Going state by state and people
by people through the Stalinist and Nazi destruction of local authority
in all the occupied smaller nations, Snyder certainly shows that those
local populations, whether Poles or Latvians or Ukrainians, could not be
instantaneously motivated to rise up and murder Jews; they could only
be very quickly motivated to do it. He seems to find more consolation in
this distinction than it may possess.
What
would be the opposite of Snyder’s view? First, that the “bloodlands”
was not a geopolitical ground that generated its own events. The worst
of the killings happened there, certainly, but there is no discernible
difference in Nazi or, for that matter, Soviet behavior elsewhere. An
entire village was murdered in central France, Jews were slaughtered en
masse on the banks of the Danube. Numbers alone, not actions, made the
bloodlands as bloody as they were. Snyder emphasizes that, where the
state was destroyed, the Nazis got at their victims more easily. It’s
certainly true that, the wider the moat, the harder it is for the tiger
to get at its victims. In France, recently arrived eastern Jews, without
friends or history, were easier to get at and deport than native French
ones. But plenty of those went to the ovens, too. Picasso’s intimate
friend, the poet and Catholic convert Max Jacob, an ornament of French
culture and as French as any man could be, died on his way to Auschwitz,
and his brother and sister were gassed on their arrival. The tiger’s
appetite, not the width of the moat, is still the story. Denmark, the
seeming counter-example, was the site of a relatively benign occupation,
in Nazi terms, but the benignity was influenced by a sense of racial
affinity, the vast irrational forces of racial hallucination seeming as
powerful as the local political forces.
Snyder
is admirably relentless in making the reader feel the horror of the
Soviet mass killings, without waving them away or moving them to the
margins. We meet, or, rather, shudder to have heard of, Vasily Blokhin,
the N.K.V.D. executioner—hard to credit as a real person and not an Ian
Fleming invention—who in one night could murder two hundred and fifty
Polish military officers. This is not being even-handed. It is being
clear-eyed. But if Snyder’s thesis is that, without the previous ten
years of Soviet brutality, the peoples of the “bloodlands” would not
have been complicit in the Nazi nightmare, then one would want more
evidence—a correlation between Soviet brutality and genocidal eagerness,
a direct relation between the two, something—to make the
correspondence more robust. In Hungary, the Arrow Cross killed with mad
vengeance, and the Béla Kun Communist period was far in the past. Vichy
passed anti-Jewish laws, and hastened its Jews toward Drancy almost
before they were asked for, and in France the Soviets were only a
spectre.
Snyder
is certainly aware of all this, and thinks that his account explains
it: “Where Germans obliterated conventional states, or annihilated
Soviet institutions that had just destroyed conventional states, they
created the abyss where racism and politics pulled together towards
nothingness.” But another view would see the obliteration as the
auxiliary act and the abyss as the central moral landscape. Politics and
procedures obviously enabled the killings; we owe Snyder a debt for his
realism about this. But the desire to maim and murder had its roots in a
disease of the mind so powerful and passionate that to call it
political or procedural hardly seems to capture its nature, or its
prevalence.
The explanation of the
human appetite for mass murder obviously does not lie in the peasant
simplicity of the Eastern Europeans. (Is there a single historian or
journalist who holds this view?) But it does seem to lie in the enduring
power of old hatreds, and our capacity for turning group hatred into
massacre, given opportune circumstance. Just as we can’t pretend that
Stalinist crimes were unrelated to absolutist Enlightenment habits of
mind in which class enemies easily become nonpersons, we can’t pretend
that the Hitlerian crimes can be released from an anti-Semitism deeply
rooted in European Christianity. The great and sympathetic historian of
Christianity Diarmaid MacCulloch writes that it is still “necessary to
remind Christians of the centuries-old heritage of anti-Semitism
festering in the memories of countless ordinary twentieth-century
Christians on the eve of the Nazi takeover. In the 1940’s, this poison
led not just Christian Germans, but Christian Lithuanians, Poles and
many others gleefully to perpetrate bestial cruelties on helpless Jews
who had done them no harm.”
And
anti-Semitism was surely different in kind from the other ethnic hatreds
of the time and place. The Jew was doubly evil, as both an agent of
modernity and the possessor of an occult mystery. Jews were
cosmopolitans, bankers, merchants, middlemen; the same family passed at
will, from day to day, as German, French, or Russian. Jews were also
possessors of an ancient text, a secret language, a lore kept hidden and
unavailable; they welcomed no converts, teaching their ancient language
reluctantly. This compound suspicion helped make anti-Semitism so
virulent. It was, as Confino shows, reflected in the sadistic Jewish
parades in which, in the thirties, helpless Jews were forced to
participate: the Torah was burned, with the enthusiastic participation
of German Christians.
Postwar
people who fastened onto the story of Anne Frank, as has been observed
before, were not in any sense sentimental to do so. That a modern state
would send the police out to entrap a fifteen-year-old girl and then
send her across Europe to her death because she was a Jew was an evil
genuinely new in the world in a way that horrific massacres (and
counter-massacres) were not. For that matter, when Martin Amis returned
to the question of Auschwitz in last year’s novel “The Zone of
Interest,” it was because he knows that it represented something
genuinely new in the practice of evil: an institution set up with all
the normal domestic appurtenances of middle-class life whose essential
purpose is the mass murder of human beings.
Snyder
offers his own view of the right lessons to draw in a final chapter of
“Black Earth,” ambitiously called “Conclusion: Our World.” The college
student’s Rwanda arrives here rapidly: just as Hitler’s world view
derived from his bizarre response to an ecological crisis—the threat to a
Germany deprived of land for growing grain—what happened in Rwanda
happened, in part, because of the exhaustion of arable land. Africa, in
Snyder’s view, may become the world’s new bloodlands, where ecological
crisis is capped by mass slaughter and where ethnic explanations of
killings (those Hutus always hated the Tutsis) conceal the political
manipulation of power.
Surely
Snyder is right when he implies that the well-meant “Godwin’s law,”
which, beginning as an observation about Internet arguments, has come to
be shorthand for the rule that the Nazis should never be introduced
into ordinary political arguments, is miscast. In fact, we should keep
the image of the Germans and the Nazis in front of us—not to show how
close the people on the other side of an argument are to unutterable
evil but to remind ourselves that we, too, can become that close in a
shorter time than we like to think. In a period of fear and panic, it is
the easiest thing in the world to talk ourselves into the idea that bad
things we do are necessities of human nature. The Germans listened to
Mozart and Beethoven and then murdered children, and this was not a
cognitive dislocation from which we couldn’t suffer but the eternal
rationale offered by the terrified: we can’t protect what really matters
if we don’t do things that we wish we didn’t have to
War
makes ordinary people do horrible things. If there is a point that
perhaps Snyder does not underline enough—it comes through vividly in
Antony Beevor’s books on the Battle of Stalingrad and other campaigns—it
is that the Germans who killed were dying, too, in increasingly vast
numbers and in cold and fear of their own. Wars make atrocities happen.
Americans have still not come to terms with My Lai, a Vietnam atrocity
not unlike the acts of the Einsatzgruppen on the Eastern Front, though
thankfully more isolated. To engage in political or procedural or even
geographic explanations of these histories misses their history. Once
panic sets in, for an army or an occupier, then the persecution—indeed,
the slaughter—of the population seems a necessity for survival.
Frightened soldiers in foreign lands murder the locals without mercy or
purpose. One wishes that this happened rarely. In truth, it happens all
the time
Yet
another truth also rises here. Hitler ruled for twelve years. The worst
of the horrors occurred during four of them. Stalin’s reign was
twenty-five-odd years. Hell on earth is possible to make but is hard to
go on making. The human appetite for social peace, if not for social
justice, eventually asserts itself. This is of no comfort to the
victims. But it should be of some comfort to the survivors, their
inheritors, and us. Those who think that the horrors of the
nineteen-thirties and forties were eclipses of the sun, rather than an
eternal darkness of the earth, are invariably mocked as Panglossian. But
Dr. Pangloss, Voltaire’s fatuously optimistic philosopher, is an
unfairly reviled man. The Enlightenment philosophers who insisted that
the world could be improved were right. Voltaire was one of them. The
mistake was to think that, once improved, it couldn’t get worse again.
Voltaire’s point was not that optimism about mankind’s fate is false. It
was that, in the face of a Heaven known to be decidedly unbenevolent,
it takes unrelenting, thankless, and mostly ill-rewarded work to
cultivate happiness here on earth, no matter what color the soil. That
was the lesson Dr. Pangloss and his students had yet to learn. ♦